5.Reality is Stranger than Fiction

By Luis M. Rocha

Lecture notes for ISE483/SSIE583 - Evolutionary Systems and Biologically Inspired Computing. Spring 2023. Systems Science and Industrial Engineering Department, Thomas J. Watson School of Engineering and Applied Science, Binghamton University. Also available in adobe acrobat pdf format


Robot and Baby


Updated from a presentation in the "Biocomplexity" discussion section at the 9th European Conference on Artificial Life, September 12, 2007 in Lisbon, Portugal

"By extending the empirical foundation upon which biology is based beyond the carbon-chain life that has evolved on Earth, Artificial Life can contribute to theoretical biology by locating life-as-we-know-it within the larger picture of life-as-it-could-be". [Langton, 1989, page 1]

From Langton’s original artificial life manifesto, the field was largely expected to free us from the confines of "life-as-we-know-it" and its specific biochemistry. The idea of "life-as-it-could-be" gave us a scientific methodology to consider and study the general principles of life at large. The main assumption of the field was that instead of focusing on the carbon-based, living organization, life could be better explained by synthesizing its "logical forms" from simple machines [Langton, 1989, page 11]—where, "fictional" machines substituted real biochemistry. The expectation was that this "out-of-the-box", synthetic methodology would deliver a wider scientific understanding of life. We would be able to entertain alternative scenarios for life, challenge the dogmas of biology, and ultimately discover the design principles of life.

Interestingly, during the 35+ years since the first artificial life workshop, biology witnessed tremendous advances in our understanding of life. True, biology operates at a completely different scale of funding and in a much larger community base than artificial life (the impact factors of key journals in both fields differ by an order of magnitude). But, still, it is from biology, not artificial life, that the strangest and most exciting discoveries and design principles of life arise today. Consider looking at the [September 6, 2007] number of Nature, with the quite apropos editorial title "Life as We Know it" [Vol. 449, 1], arguing for a comparative genomics approach, with articles, for instance, moving towards evolutionary principles of gene duplication [Wapinski et al, 2007]. Publications in the [September 2007 issue of] PLoS. Biol., also presented new evidence towards updating or discovering general principles of life: for instance, Venter’s sequencing of his diploid genome, which updates our expectations of differences in chromosome pairs [Levy et al, 2007]), and the Ahituv et al [2007] study that challenges the idea that utraconserved DNA (across species) must be functional. Since then, many advances, often enabled by big data approaches of computational biology, keep being discovered; for instance, from large-scale comparative genomics, it has been found that retroviral genomic sequences account for 6 to 14% of host genomes---~8% of human DNA is from endogenous retroviruses, which comprises more DNA than the human proteome [Weiss & Stoye, 2013].

It is good to notice that this sort of work is not so much an exception, but has been a signature of research in the biosciences in the last couple of decades. Consider cases such as the discovery of DNA transfer from bacteria to the fly [Dunning Hotopp, 2007], extra-genomic inheritance in Arabidopsis [Lolle et al, 2005], or the profound importance of non-coding RNA in life which is a major player in, among other features, patterning [Martello et al, 2007] , essential gene regulation [Mattick, 2005], development [Mattick, 2007], epigenetic neural development and modulation [Mehler & Mattick, 2007; Mattick & Mehler, 2008], eukariotic complexity [Taft et al, 2007], etc. Moreover, advances such as these do not seem to be mere epiphenomena of a specific life form. Indeed, they point at important organization principles---as those that artificial life was supposed to provide. When we discover that non-transcribed RNA is involved in extra-genomic inheritance or that most of the evolutionary innovation responsible for differences between marsupials and placental mammals occurs in non-protein coding DNA [Mikkelsen et al, 2007], some fundamental principles of the living organization are to be re-thought: the simple, generalized genotype-phenotype mappings on which most of artificial life is based on, are just not enough to capture the principles of life as we know it. More intricate genomic structure, and its principles, need to be modeled and theories need to be built to understand life.

One could go on and on about many other advances in biology—CRISPR [Ledford, 2017], the pangenome [Beavan et al 2024], and even Horizontal Gene Transfer involved in “parasitic mind control” [Wilcox , 2023] come to mind, especially as examples of the extended role of DNA and its ability to encode information and facilitate exchanges between very open organisms. We can also point to themes at the forefront of (bio)complexity theory that go largely overlooked in artificial life---though not completely (i.e. [Calabretta et al, 2000; Hintze & Adami, 2007]). Nonetheless, looking at the papers accepted for the main sections of the latest Alife and ECAL conferences, it is easy to see that most papers, not only do not discover or even address such issues, but largely trade in biological and computational concepts that have not changed much since the field’s inception (see list of top themes and terms in appendix). Is artificial life trapped in the (evolutionary) biology of twenty years ago? Why is reality stranger and more surprising than fiction?

Clearly, there has been very widely successful artificial life research. First and foremost, artificial life has been most successful as a means to study animal behavior, learning and cognition. Certainly, evolutionary robotics and embodied cognition have had an impact in cognitive science. But is artificial life simply a better way to do artificial intelligence? Moreover, one could argue that given the embodied nature of evolutionary robotics, it would seem that it is bound to some kind of material reality, rather than synthesized by constituent "logical forms" as Langton initially suggested.

But what to do about the organization of life itself? Surely the idea of explaining the living organization was behind the origin of the field. For the purposes of this discussion, we must question ourselves why artificial life does not produce more and surprising results about the living organization? Certainly, there is sound research in the field with impact outside of it [e.g. Adami, 2006; Hintze & Adami, 2007]. But even the most successful research in artificial life rarely goes beyond showing that artificial organisms can observe the same behaviors as their real counterparts (i.e. selective pressures, epistasis, etc.). A problem for the field is that as biotechnology gains more and more control of cellular processes, it is reasonable to ask what can one do with artificial organisms that one cannot do with real bacteria? For instance, recent studies of the evolutionary speed towards beneficial mutations were quite effectively done with E-coli [Perfeito et al, 2007], pointing to a much larger rate of beneficial mutations in bacteria than previously thought, and shedding new light on the general principal of clonal interference.

Certainly the community can think of a variety of responses to this lack of new principles of life coming out of research in artificial life—even in theoretical biology. One concept that I venture may need updating in artificial life is its view of the genotype/phenotype relationship. Langton proposed that we generalize this relationship, but this meant that research in the field largely regarded the two as indistinguishable. While this move at fist glance seems appropriate to deal with the complexity of genomic-proteomic interaction, it prevents us from studying the specific roles each plays in the living organization. Genotype and phenotype are intertwined in a complex manner, but each operates under different principles that are often overlooked in artificial life. Thus, artificial life rarely approaches issues of genomic structure and regulation, or the co-existence of DNA and RNA as different types of informational carriers. This could well be because artificial life models seem to trade most often on the concept of Mendelian gene than on the molecular biology gene. In other words, artificial life models tend to regard genes solely as mechanisms of generational (vertical) inheritance, rather than as (informational) mechanisms of ontogenetic (horizontal) development, regulation, maintenance, phenotypic plasticity, and response to environmental change. This way, most artificial life models do not test, or even deal with, possible genomic structure architectures and their impact on development and evolution. This is a big shortcoming in the field since, as we have seen in the last two decades, the molecular biology gene and the genomic structure it implies are behind many essential principles of life—from hypersomatic mutation in vertebrate immunity to speciation.

Additionally, it is most often the case that artificial organisms in artificial life models are designed with many top-down features, rather than emerging out of artificial biochemical machines. For instance, typically the genes of artificial organisms encode pre-defined computer operations. Not only is the encoding pre-defined, but the function of individual genes is also pre-programmed, rather than emergent from some artificial chemistry—what is typically emergent is the behavior of a collection of such "atomic" genes and genotypes.

It is interesting to note that when biologists were looking for the location of genetic information for inheritance, they naturally assumed that it would reside in proteins. They knew of DNA chemically, but its sheer inertness deemed it unfit for the job, because of the theoretical expectations set up Schrödinger [1944] that the molecules responsible for genetic inheritance should behave as a "codescript," i.e. a molecule that could simultaneously function as memory store and engage in catalysis and auto-catalysis. Since catalysis required highly active, dynamical biomolecules, Schrödinger’s disciples, who controlled all early molecular biology, were looking for proteins or something similar. It took some time to realize that relative inertness was really the point, from Griffith’s experiment in 1928 to Avery, MacLeod, and McCarty’s in 1944 when DNA was identified as the carrier of genetic information—the implications of which were only fully accepted much later , probably costing Avery a deserved Nobel [Judson, 2003]. Even Avery and team took at least a decade to hit on DNA after Griffiths experiment, because they first tried to knock out all cellular constituents that were dynamic. The last thing Schrödinger 's theory allowed him to consider was something so inert as DNA. But of course, inertness is necessary for matter to function as memory (see Chapter 6).

This episode illustrates how reality very often surprises the best scientific expectations of the day—a big problem for Artificial Life, as long as it defines itself as the study of life-as-it-could-be, since it implies a science built on what scientists think life is and not on what experiments show it is. For instance, the biochemical difference between highly inert memory molecules and highly reactive, functional ones, while often overlooked in artificial life as a design principle, is ultimately the hallmark of life [Rocha and Hordijk, 2005; Brenner, 2012]. Indeed, Venter’s achievement in successfully replicating a living cell with a "prosthetic genome" until the original organism’s phenotype is fully re-programmed (see chapter 1), should lead Artificial Life scientists to ponder at least the question of what is it about life’s design principle that makes it easier to synthesize a working prosthetic genome than a working "prosthetic" proteome or metabolome? Perhaps, Langton’s view of artificial life being built-up from simple machines, may have clouded the fact that life as we know it is made of biochemical constituents with very different chemical and functional roles: chiefly, DNA (long-term, random-access memory), RNA (short-term memory and symbol processing) and proteins (functional machines). Perhaps more attention should be directed to the "logical forms" of these structural constituents that produce life, before we can tackle "life-as-it-could-be".

I am extremely grateful to the late Karola Stotz (when she spent time at Indiana University) for the exciting conversations that directly lead to this text. I also thank Janet Wiles for performing the Leximancer analysis, and Peter Todd for patiently listening as some of the ideas here discussed were germinating.

Ahituv, N., et al. [2007]. "Deletion of Ultraconserved Elements Yields Viable Mice". PLoS Biology Vol. 5, No. 9, e234.

Beavan, Alan, Maria Rosa Domingo-Sananes, and James O. McInerney. [2024] “Contingency, Repeatability, and Predictability in the Evolution of a Prokaryotic Pangenome.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 121 (1): e2304934120. DOI: 10.1073/pnas.2304934120.

Brenner, S. [2012]. "Turing centenary: Life’s code script." Nature 482 (7386): 461-461.

Calabretta, R., Nolfi, S., Parisi, D. and Wagner, G.P. [2000]. "Duplication of modules facilitates the evolution of functional specialization". Artificial Life, 6 , 69-84.

Hintze, A. and C. Adami [2007]. "Evolution of complex modular biological networks". arXiv.org:0705.4674.

Dunning Hotopp, J. C., et al. [2007] "Widespread Lateral Gene Transfer from Intracellular Bacteria to Multicellular Eukaryotes," Science doi:10.1126.

Judson, H.F. [2003]. "No Nobel Prize for Whining". New York Times, October 20, 2003.

Ledford, Heidi. [2017] “Five Big Mysteries about CRISPR’s Origins.” Nature 541 (7637): 280–82. DOI: 10.1038/541280a.

Levy, S. et al. [2007] PLoS Biol. 5, e254.

Lolle, S. J., et al [2005]. "Genome-wide non-mendelian inheritance of extra-genomic information in Arabidopsis", Nature 434, 505-509.

Mikkelsen, T.S. et al [2007]. "Genome of the marsupial Monodelphis domestica reveals innovation in non-coding sequences". Nature 447, 167-177.

Martello, G. Et al [2007]. "MicroRNA control of Nodal signalling" Nature. doi:10.1038/nature06100;

Mattick, J.S. [2005] "The functional genomics of noncoding RNA". Science. 309 (5740): 1570-3.

Mattick JS.[2007]. "A new paradigm for developmental biology". J Exp Biol. ;210(Pt 9):1526-47

Mattick, JS & MF Mehler [2008] "RNA editing, DNA recoding and the evolution of human cognition". Trends in Neurosciences, 31 (5):227-233.

Mehler MF, Mattick JS. [2007]. "Noncoding RNAs and RNA editing in brain development, functional diversification, and neurological disease". Physiol Rev. 87(3):799-823

Perfeito L, L. Fernandes, C. Mota and I. Gordo [2007]. "Adaptive Mutations in Bacteria: High Rate and Small Effects". Science. 317 (5839):813 - 815.

Rocha, L.M. and W. Hordijk [2005]. "Material Representations: From the Genetic Code to the Evolution of Cellular Automata". Artificial Life. 11 (1-2):189 - 214

Schrödinger, Erwin [1944]. What is Life? Cambridge University Press.

Taft RJ, Pheasant M, Mattick JS. [2007]."The relationship between non-protein-coding DNA and eukaryotic complexity". Bioessays. 29(3):288-99.

Wapinski, I., A. Pfeffer, N. Friedman, and A. Regev [2007]. "Natural history and evolutionary principles of gene duplication in fungi". Nature 449, 54-61.1.

Weiss & Stoye [2013]. "Our Viral Inheritance." Science.340 (6134): 820-821

Wilcox, Christie. [2023] “Parasitic Worms May Control Minds of Insects with ‘Borrowed’ Genes.” Science, DOI: 10.1126/science.adl4678.


Last Modified: March 26, 2024